Lim Toh Han

Justice in its Fullest Orb: The Evolving Relationship Between Procedure and Substantive Law (II/II)

The PDF version of this article can be found here.


 

Justice in its fullest orb: the evolving relationship between procedure and substantive law (ii/ii)

 

lim toh han*

 

I.                    Introduction

 

This two-part article considers how various High Court and Court of Appeal cases from 2001 to 2020 show that procedure has been made coequal with substantive law, and how this shift to coequality has occurred in two stages:

(a)    From resolving the tension between procedure and substantive law as separate conceptions of justice (“to resolve this tension”, in the words of Andrew Phang JC, as his Honour then was[1]) – discussed in Part I;

(b)   To balancing procedure and substantive law as integrated aspects of the orb of justice (“to integrate … justice”, in Andrew Phang JC’s words[2]) – discussed in Part II (this Part).


 

II.                 “To integrate justice”

 

More recent cases have adopted a conceptually different approach. Procedure and substantive law are not conflicting concepts in a tension to be resolved, but harmonious aspects of the orb of justice to be integrated. The following propositions may be distilled from the cases:

 

A.  The Balance of Justice

 

First, the court will weigh the procedural and substantive aspects of the case to locate the balance of justice. This judicial discretion is guided, not by rules, but by the following principles:

 

1.      Procedural Merits

 

One, procedural merits are not about the technical procedural rights of parties, but the procedural conduct of parties and the spirit of procedural rules. In United Overseas Bank Ltd v Ng Huat Foundations Pte Ltd [UOB],[3] Andrew Phang JC dismissed an application to stay winding-up proceedings, pending an appeal against Lai Kew Chai J’s dismissal of an application for a scheme of arrangement. The substantive merits clearly favoured the respondent.[4] The procedural merits also favoured the respondent; the applicant’s long string of procedural applications was merely “another device … to stave off what appeared … inevitabl[e]”,[5] the respondent had endured “continued and unjustified delay”, and the applicant could still sue after winding-up (albeit by its liquidator).[6] The court was unimpressed by the applicant’s plea for “procedural justice”,[7] which were really technical procedural rights. Subsequently, in Liberty Sky Investments Ltd v Aesthetic Medical Partners Pte Ltd,[8] a claim for fraudulent misrepresentation, Andrew Phang JA rejected the representee’s argument that the trial court had erroneously refused rescission as the representor had not pled any bars to rescission (as was the representor’s onus to). Not only was the representee’s argument “rather arid and technical”; it was “antithetical to the very spirit of the rules of pleading”, because in this (somewhat unusual) case, it was the representee (rather than the representor) who had exclusive knowledge of the facts underlying potential bars to rescission.[9] Furthermore, the representee had knowledge of the representor’s arguments on potential bars to rescission, and had even written a letter to the trial court rebutting those arguments.[10]

Two, procedural merits may need to be balanced between the parties. Such balancing was evident in Lea Tool and Moulding Industries Pte Ltd v CGU International Insurance plc [Lea Tools],[11] where neither party’s procedural conduct was satisfactory (leading the court to dismiss the application initially),[12] though the balance tipped in the plaintiff’s favour (since the court allowed the application only on further arguments).[13]

Three, procedural merits may need to be balanced between the parties and the public. In the administration of justice, the public interest weighs more heavily than the parties’ interests. In Alliance Management SA v Pendleton Lane P [Alliance],[14] the High Court struck out the defence of a party which deliberately disregarded court orders regarding evidence. This was not to punish but to prevent injustice (whether to the other party in the proceedings, or to other litigants generally, with their demands on the court’s limited resources),[15] because irrespective of the possibility of a fair trial, total disregard of court rules or orders amounts to abuse of process.[16]

Four, the adequacy of compensation by costs is a significant, but not determinative, factor. In Eller, Urs v Cheong Kiat Wah,[17] the High Court made a bifurcation order even though the plaintiff only effectively requested bifurcation in closing submissions[18] (rather than before the trial commenced). Any prejudice to the defendant was “readily compensated by costs” as it was “very slight” (at best), because first, a bifurcation order would almost certainly have been granted if the plaintiff had applied for bifurcation timeously,[19] and second, the defendant had not called expert witnesses to rebut the plaintiff’s submissions on quantum[20] (and spent any money or effort doing so). By contrast, in Alliance,[21] the High Court struck out the disobedient party’s defence to liability (though it was allowed to take part on the question of quantum).[22] This reflects the principle that, while adjudication will ordinarily not be denied if costs adequately compensate the aggrieved party, it will be denied if demanded by the public interest on balance (as this case demanded).[23]

 

2.      Substantive Merits

 

Five, in weighing substantive merits, the court may need to form a view of the substantive case:

(a)    If liability and remedies have been tried, the court already has a final view of the substantive merits. For example, in Lee Chee Wei v Tan Hor Peow Victor [Lee Chee Wei],[24] where a non-bifurcated trial[25] had taken place, the Court of Appeal could form the view that an order for assessment of damages in lieu of specific performance (which the trial judge had refused to make[26]) was appropriate.[27]

(b)   If not, the court may need to form a provisional view of the substantive merits:

(i)             It may be clear where the substantive justice lies. For example, in UOB,[28] even though the principal petition was still being heard,[29] the “long string of procedural applications”[30] made it clear where the substantive justice lay.[31]

(ii)           If not, the court will likely not require proof on a balance of probabilities. For example, in Lea Tools,[32] the court considered it sufficient that there were triable issues (as summary judgment had been refused[33]).

(c)    Nonetheless, a provisional view may be impossible or unnecessary where evidence is deliberately made unavailable (eg in K Solutions Pte Ltd v National University of Singapore[34] and Alliance[35]).

Six, the claim amount is also a factor. In Lee Chee Wei,[36] the Court of Appeal ordered damages to be assessed, despite the plaintiff’s failure to plead for damages “to be assessed” and to adduce evidence on damages.[37] While the latter “le[ft] much to be desired”,[38] the court seemed moved by “the princely consideration of $4.5m”, which was “anything but small change”.[39] (The former was not prejudicial, as the words “to be assessed” were “superfluous”.[40]) By contrast, in Edmund Tie & Co (SEA) Pte Ltd v Savills Residential Pte Ltd [Edmund Tie],[41] the High Court did not allow the plaintiff, who had pleaded for a particular amount of damages without the words “or such sums as the court deems fit”, to claim a different amount of damages. The court emphasised that “the amount involved is only $13,385.70, at best, or just $6,255”.[42] (The court also emphasised that the plaintiff made no attempt to rectify its inadequately pleaded case.[43])

 

3.      Fact Sensitivity

 

Seven, the exercise is fact-sensitive. The opposite outcomes in Lee Chee Wei[44] and Edmund Tie,[45] despite apparently similar facts, show that “previous decisions [are] no more than guides”.[46]

 

4.      No Procedure-Substance Dichotomy

 

Eight, the procedural and substantive aspects need not be distinguished as such in every case. While often convenient, the procedure-substance dichotomy sometimes obscures the true principle: the court balances, not procedure on the one hand and substance on the other hand, but all procedural and substantive aspects of the case in a manner inadequately described by a two-handed metaphor. For example, in Sun Jin Engineering Pte Ltd v Hwang Jae Woo,[47] the Court of Appeal allowed a late application for stay of proceedings based on various factors: the applicant’s lateness was unintentional, the application was not without merit, and the application did not pertain to a notice of appeal.[48] Under the classical approach, these factors must be classified as procedural or substantive before a tension arises. One might argue all the factors are procedural; another might argue that the application’s merits are a substantive aspect of procedural justice. But under the integrated approach, such a fruitless inquiry is unnecessary.

 

B.  The Importance of Procedure

 

Second, procedure remains an important aspect of the orb of justice.

Courts constantly enjoin litigants to observe procedural discipline. But the Court of Appeal dramatically enjoined judges to do the same in AXM v AXO,[49] where it considered whether an interim maintenance order could be retrospectively lowered. While substantive justice was not in issue, Andrew Phang JA’s concern was the procedural pathway to the substantive outcome.[50] As a matter of statutory interpretation, an interim maintenance order could not be retrospectively overridden[51] or varied by a final maintenance order.[52] Inherent power was inapt.[53] Instead, a final maintenance order should be (prospectively) made based on retrospective considerations.[54] His Honour concluded that “on the facts at hand … a substantively just and fair result can be achieved in accordance with [procedure]”.[55]

The message is clear: procedure is not just an aspect of the orb of justice that occasionally recedes out of sight as the orb rotates. Even without tensions to resolve, the task of integrating justice remains at hand, for procedural discipline is also justice.

 

C.  The Place of Ethics

 

Third, ethics must be an important aspect of the orb of justice. Apart from its fundamental importance to a noble and honourable profession,[56] ethics also affects the administration of justice.

Lock Han Chng Jonathan v Goh Jessiline[57] was a dispute over merely $60.35 that reached the Court of Appeal. The Court of Appeal ordered the plaintiff’s solicitor not to tax his solicitor-and-client costs before disciplinary investigations concluded.[58] Lam Hwa Engineering & Trading Pte Ltd v Yang Qiang[59] was not only a dispute over merely $1,208 that reached the Court of Appeal, but also an appeal with “absolutely no merit” (the defendant’s solicitor quoted a 17th-century Lord Coke commentary and a 19th-century case on a 21st-century Rules of Court issue, which was both irrelevant[60] and erroneous[61]). The Court of Appeal ordered the defendant’s solicitor’s law firm to bear the plaintiff’s costs on an indemnity basis.[62]

These decisions evince the court’s readiness to use procedural mechanisms to address ethical considerations. Indeed, in these cases, costs struck an optimum balance between binding a principal to their agent’s acts and imposing liability on the actual wrongdoer. However, where costs do not adequately compensate (eg where land is involved), a more difficult balance may need to be found between the procedural, substantive and ethical merits of the case.


 

D.  Limitations

 

Finally, the orb of justice need not be slavishly applied in well-developed areas of civil procedure. For example, setting aside irregular default judgments is already governed by established Mercurine[63] principles, which embody the orb principle at a less abstract level. An analogy[64] is the Spandeck[65] test in negligence, which is in theory universal, but in practice applied only in novel situations.[66]

 

III.              Conclusion

 

Where will the orb of justice next turn? The history of physics provides an instructive parallel. For millennia, space (with its three dimensions) and time were considered separate concepts. Only by Albert Einstein were they unified as four dimensions of the same thing – spacetime.[67] Hermann Minkowski, his ex-teacher, famously hailed thus: “Henceforth, space by itself, and time by itself, are doomed to fade away into mere shadows, and only a kind of union of the two shall [be feasible].”[68] This was hyperbolic, for today, physics remains divided into two branches: classical physics, which separates space and time and is sufficient for most situations, and modern physics, which unifies spacetime and is necessary only for extreme conditions.

Similarly, well-developed areas of civil procedure are governed by established principles. Even in the less-developed areas of civil procedure, most cases can be resolved using the classical approach. Only in the most difficult cases does the integrated approach come vividly to the fore, and “justice in its fullest orb … shine forth”.[69]

 



*LLB (First Class Honours) (NUS), LLM (Melb) (w.e.f. 26 July 2020). A version of this article was submitted as a mid-term assignment for the NUS Law module LL4413 Civil Justice and Procedure. I would like to thank Professor Jeffrey Pinsler, SC (Geoffrey Bartholomew Professor, NUS Law) for his kind and helpful comments. All errors and views expressed in this article remain my own.

 

[1] United Overseas Bank Ltd v Ng Huat Foundations Pte Ltd [2005] 2 SLR(R) 425, [2005] SGHC 50 at [9] [emphasis removed].

[2] Ibid.

[3] [2005] 2 SLR(R) 425, [2005] SGHC 50 [UOB].

[4] Ibid at [16]. I use “applicant” and “respondent” to refer to the applicant and respondent in this stay application (rather than the respondent and applicant, respectively, in the principal winding-up petition).

[5] Ibid at [17].

[6] Ibid at [41] [emphasis removed].

[7] Ibid at [14] [emphasis removed].

[8] [2020] 1 SLR 606, [2020] SGCA 7.

[9] Ibid at [16] [emphasis removed].

[10] Ibid at [15].

[11] [2000] 3 SLR(R) 745, [2000] SGHC 241 [Lea Tools]. “Lea Tool” and “Lea Tools” were used interchangeably by the court.

[12] Ibid at [17].

[13] Ibid at [18], [22].

[14] [2008] 4 SLR(R) 1, [2008] SGHC 76 [Alliance].

[15] Ibid at [9].

[16] Ibid at [13].

[17] [2020] SGHC 106.

[18] Ibid at [137].

[19] Ibid at [142].

[20] Ibid at [143].

[21] Alliance, supra note 14.

[22] Ibid at [45].

[23] Ibid at [6]–[7].

[24] [2007] 3 SLR(R) 537, [2007] SGCA 22 [Lee Chee Wei].

[25] Ibid at [64].

[26] Ibid at [57].

[27] Ibid at [80].

[28] UOB, supra note 3.

[29] Ibid at [10].

[30] Ibid at [15] [emphasis removed].

[31] Ibid at [16].

[32] Lea Tools, supra note 11.

[33] Ibid at [3], [21].

[34] [2009] 4 SLR(R) 254, [2009] SGHC 143.

[35] Alliance, supra note 14.

[36] Lee Chee Wei, supra note 24.

[37] Ibid at [62], [72], [80].

[38] Ibid.

[39] Ibid at [65].

[40] Ibid at [62].

[41] [2018] 5 SLR 349, [2018] SGHC 84 [Edmund Tie].

[42] Ibid at [8].

[43] Ibid at [11].

[44] Lee Chee Wei, supra note 24.

[45] Edmund Tie, supra note 41.

[46] Sun Jin Engineering Pte Ltd v Hwang Jae Woo [2011] 2 SLR 196, [2011] SGCA 4 at [30].

[47] [2011] 2 SLR 196, [2011] SGCA 4.

[48] Ibid at [45].

[49] [2014] 2 SLR 705, [2014] SGCA 13.

[50] Ibid at [36].

[51] Ibid at [19]–[20].

[52] Ibid at [29].

[53] Ibid at [23].

[54] See ibid at [29]–[30], [35]–[37].

[55] Ibid at [30].

[56] See Legal Profession (Professional Conduct) Rules 2015 (S 706/2015), r 7(1), Principle (a).

[57] [2008] 2 SLR(R) 455, [2007] SGCA 56.

[58] Ibid at [47].

[59] [2014] 2 SLR 191, [2014] SGCA 3.

[60] Ibid at [24].

[61] Ibid at [25].

[62] Ibid at [42]–[43].

[63] Mercurine Pte Ltd v Canberra Development Pte Ltd [2008] 4 SLR(R) 907, [2008] SGCA 38.

[64] In AXM v AXO [2014] 2 SLR 705, [2014] SGCA 13 at [23], Andrew Phang JA noted parallels between procedural law and negligence law, such as the applicability of the floodgates argument.

[65] Spandeck Engineering (S) Pte Ltd v Defence Science & Technology Agency [2007] 4 SLR(R) 100, [2007] SGCA 37.

[66] See ibid at [73].

[67] Albert Einstein, “On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies” (1905) 322:10 Annalen der Physik 891, set out two postulates of special relativity (the principle of relativity and the principle of invariant light speed). A consequence of the postulates was that space and time were inseparable. Subsequently, Hermann Minkowski, “The Union of Space and Time” (Address delivered at the 80th Assembly of German Natural Scientists and Physicians, 21 September 1908) in Milič Čapek, ed, The Concepts of Space and Time: Their Structure and Their Development (Dordrecht: D Reidel Publishing Co, 1976) 339, developed a mathematical model of special relativity that unified space and time (although, to be precise, it treated the dimension of time differently from the three dimensions of space). Eventually, Minkowski’s model was used by Albert Einstein, “The Foundation of the General Theory of Relativity” (1916) 49:7 Annalen der Physik 769, to develop general relativity.

[68] Hermann Minkowski, “The Union of Space and Time” (Address delivered at the 80th Assembly of German Natural Scientists and Physicians, 21 September 1908) in Milič Čapek, ed, The Concepts of Space and Time: Their Structure and Their Development (Dordrecht: D Reidel Publishing Co, 1976) 339 at 339.

[69] UOB, supra note 3 at [9].

Justice in its Fullest Orb: The Evolving Relationship Between Procedure and Substantive Law (I/II)

The PDF version of this article can be found here.


 

justice in its fullest orb: the evolving relationship between procedure and substantive law (i/II)

 

lim toh han*

 

I.                    Introduction

Common-law procedure has come a long way since England’s royal courts of justice were established in the 12th century. For centuries, procedure was the law; the common law was called “a law of procedure” with “whatever substantive law … hidden … in its ‘interstices’”.[1]

Following the 19th-century Judicature Acts,[2] procedure was made subservient to substantive law. Sir Richard Collins MR (as his Lordship then was) memorably described procedure as a “handmaid” (a servant of a household) rather than a “mistress” (a controller of a household)[3]:

Although … a Court cannot conduct its business without a code of procedure … the relation of rules of practice to the work of justice is intended to be that of handmaid rather than mistress, and the Court ought not to be so far bound and tied by rules, which are after all only intended as general rules of procedure, as to be compelled to do what will cause injustice in the particular case.[4]

Since this century’s turn, procedure has been made coequal with substantive law. VK Rajah JA (as his Honour then was) described procedure as the servant, not of substantive law, but of the “overriding objective” of “even handed justice”:

The rules of court practice and procedure exist to provide a convenient framework to facilitate dispute resolution and to serve the ultimate and overriding objective of justice. Such an objective must never be eclipsed by blind or pretended fealty to rules of procedure. On the other hand, a pragmatic approach governed by justice as its overarching aim should not be viewed as a charter to ignore procedural requirements. In the ultimate analysis, each case involving procedural lapses or mishaps must be assessed in its proper factual matrix and calibrated by reference to the paramount rationale of dispensing even handed justice.[5]

More dramatically, Andrew Phang JC (as his Honour then was) described procedure and substantive law as two facets of one “orb” of justice:

The quest for justice … entails a continuous need to balance the procedural with the substantive. More than that, it is a continuous attempt to ensure that both are integrated, as far as that is humanly possible. Both interact with each other. One cannot survive without the other. There must, therefore, be – as far as is possible – a fair and just procedure that leads to a fair and just result. This is not merely abstract theorising. It is the very basis of what the courts do – and ought to do. When in doubt, the courts would do well to keep these bedrock principles in mind …

It is true, however, that in the sphere of practical reality, there is often a tension between the need for procedural justice on the one hand and substantive justice on the other. The task of the court is to attempt … to resolve this tension. There is a further task: it is to actually attempt, simultaneously, to integrate these two conceptions of justice in order that justice in its fullest orb may shine forth.[6]

Building on Professor Jeffrey Pinsler, SC and Cavinder Bull, SC’s seminal work,[7] which covered cases from 2005 to 2010,[8] this two-part article examines various High Court and Court of Appeal cases from 2001 to 2020, most of which are expressed in terms of the orb of justice or even-handed justice. It considers how these cases show that procedure has been made coequal with substantive law, and how this shift to coequality has occurred in two stages:

(a)    From resolving the tension between procedure and substantive law as separate conceptions of justice (“to resolve this tension”, in Andrew Phang JC’s words[9]) – discussed in Part I (this Part);

(b)   To balancing procedure and substantive law as integrated aspects of the orb of justice (“to integrate … justice”, in Andrew Phang JC’s words[10]) – discussed in Part II.

 

II.                 “To resolve this tension”

 

Classically (at least following the Judicature Acts[11]), the common law has been bifurcated between procedure and substantive law, perhaps in line with 19th-century English lawyers’ tendency to classify the world into binary sets. This sets up a tension which the cases have resolved in several ways:

(a)    For a long time, procedure was subservient to substantive law – discussed in section II(A).

(b)   Recently, procedure has become more dominant, whether:

(i)             In protection of substantive law – discussed in section II(B); or

(ii)           In collaboration with substantive law – discussed in section II(C)

(c)    Fundamentally, procedure is the very means by which substantive law is effectuated – discussed in section II(D).

 

A.      Procedure Yields to Substantive Law

 

First, procedure yields to substantive law in the interest of justice, though as an equal “spouse” rather than a subordinate “handmaid” shoved aside by substantive law.

Perhaps the pioneering case in this shift to coequality is Lea Tool and Moulding Industries Pte Ltd v CGU International Insurance plc,[12] where the High Court set aside a judgment in default of compliance with an unless order. Substantive justice favoured setting aside the default judgment: the claim was “substantial” (slightly under $1.5m) and there were triable issues (summary judgment had been refused).[13] The balance of procedural justice was less clear: on the one hand, the application to set aside the default judgment was nearly three years late; on the other hand, the applicant’s non-compliance with the unless order was “minor”, and the respondent’s failure to highlight the potential irregularity to the registrar (when the respondent should have) contributed to the irregularity of the registrar’s default judgment.[14] Ultimately, the court held that the applicant “should not be deprived of the benefit of an insurance cover merely because of a minor [procedural] irregularity”,[15] as “procedural laws are ultimately handmaidens to help us achieve the ultimate and only objective of achieving justice”.[16]

The decision, while expressed in the language of subservient “handmaidens”, foreshadows procedure’s new role as a coequal “spouse” on closer inspection. Initially, the court was not inclined to set aside the default judgment.[17] After further arguments,[18] the court was persuaded that the balance of procedural justice tipped in favour of setting aside the default judgment.[19] Thus, procedure was not violently shoved aside by, but gently yielded to, substantive law in the interest of justice.

 

B.      Procedure Protects Substantive Law

 

Second, procedure protects substantive law’s integrity.

In K Solutions Pte Ltd v National University of Singapore,[20] the High Court struck out the claim of a party who deliberately destroyed documents. The court held that the possibility of a fair trial depended, not only on the availability of documents, but also the reasons for any unavailability of documents:[21]

(a)    If the destruction was deliberate, and:

(i)             If important documents were unavailable, striking out would be appropriate.[22]

(ii)           If important documents remained available, striking out would not necessarily be appropriate, depending on the availability of other documents.[23]

(b)   If the destruction was reckless or negligent, striking out would depend on a variety of considerations.[24]

(c)    If the destruction was innocent, even if important documents were unavailable, striking out “must be rare”.[25]

This intricate classification reveals a nuanced approach towards protecting substantive law’s integrity. A fair trial is impossible if important documents are deliberately destroyed. But a fair trial remains possible even if important documents are innocently destroyed, or unimportant documents are deliberately destroyed. Indeed, striking out may even occasion substantive injustice, as “… perfect justice … would actually defeat justice”.[26]

 

C.     Procedure Collaborates with Substantive Law

 

Third, procedure collaborates with substantive law to achieve the policy of the law. While policy has long been derided as a “very unruly horse”,[27] the twin whips of procedure and substantive law can be helpful in taming this workhorse.[28]

In Greenline-Onyx Envirotech Phils, Inc v Otto Systems Singapore Pte Ltd [Greenline],[29] the Court of Appeal admitted into evidence a letter which was both a without-prejudice communication and an acknowledgement of debt. It held that the letter fell within all three solutions in Bradford & Bingley plc v Rashid [Bradford][30] to the question of the admissibility of without-prejudice acknowledgements, without endorsing either the majority’s, Lord Hoffmann’s, or Lord Hope’s solution.[31]

Greenline remains to be explained in terms of which Bradford solution(s) apply in Singapore (even if, strictly speaking, the discussion on the admissibility of without-prejudice acknowledgements were obiter, as the ratio turned on the waiver of privilege[32]), for three reasons. First, Greenline was applied without explanation by the Court of Appeal in Fairview Developments Pte Ltd v Ong & Ong Pte Ltd,[33] in admitting a without-prejudice acknowledgement.[34] Second, Greenline was applied at some length by the High Court in Cytec Industries Pte Ltd v APP Chemicals International (Mau) Ltd [Cytec],[35] which preferred the majority’s solution, and noted that Lord Hoffmann’s solution was subsequently disapproved by the UK House of Lords (while ultimately leaving the question to the Court of Appeal).[36] Third, Bradford’s solutions should be reconsidered in Singapore, where both the without-prejudice rule and the acknowledgement rule are statutory rules embodying Parliament’s intent.[37]

Procedure’s collaboration with substantive law can partly explain which Bradford solution(s) should apply in Singapore. The basis for this collaboration is the policy of encouraging settlements shared by the Limitation Act[38] and the Evidence Act;[39] the High Court in Cytec[40] observed that both the without-prejudice rule and the acknowledgement rule have the policy of encouraging settlements.[41] A recent exercise in identifying a policy shared by two statutes is UKM v Attorney-General [UKM],[42] where Sundaresh Menon CJ held that the Adoption of Children Act’s[43] specific provisions on child adoption were “supplemented by” the Guardianship of Infants Act’s general provision for the paramountcy of the child’s welfare,[44] so that the policy of the paramountcy of the child’s welfare was shared by both statutes.[45]

Collaboration favours the majority’s solution – that the without-prejudice rule does not apply to apparently open communications designed only to discuss the repayment of an admitted liability, rather than to negotiate the existence and extent of a disputed liability[46] (which was preferred by the High Court in Cytec[47]). The majority’s solution is not unlike Lord Hope’s solution – that the without-prejudice rule does not apply to “clear admissions or statements of fact”, which do “not form part of the offer to compromise”.[48] Both solutions achieve the policy shared by the without-prejudice rule and the acknowledgement rule – to keep claims out of court.[49] Otherwise, to exclude without-prejudice acknowledgements, even if they clearly admit the existence or extent of liability, not only does nothing to achieve the (other) policy of the without-prejudice rule – to encourage parties to reach agreement[50] (presumably, because agreement has already been reached); but also undermines the policy of the acknowledgement rule – to keep claims out of court (because creditors will be forced to litigate, if the limitation clock cannot be reset by acknowledgement).[51] Indeed, both solutions not only represent collaboration between procedure and substantive law, but would also give full effect to the Singapore Parliament’s intent.

Collaboration is inconsistent with Lord Hoffmann’s solution – that the without-prejudice rule does not apply to acknowledgements,[52] unless parties agree that anything said in negotiations cannot be used as acknowledgements[53] (which was subsequently disapproved by the UK House of Lords, as noted by the High Court in Cytec[54]). Lord Hoffmann’s solution effectively emasculates the without-prejudice rule in the context of acknowledgements (since, as his Lordship acknowledges, parties in this context are unlikely to agree that anything said in negotiations cannot be used as acknowledgements, as creditors will realise that debtors are trying to run down the limitation clock[55]). Indeed, Lord Hoffmann’s solution not only represents the triumph of procedure over substantive law (albeit a largely hollow triumph since, as his Lordship acknowledges, “[q]uestions of evidence to prove the debt will arise later”[56]); it is also questionable in Singapore, where the without-prejudice rule is a statutory rule embodying Parliament’s intent, rather than a “general public policy” as in England and Wales.[57]

Furthermore, collaboration is inconsistent with Lord Hoffmann’s justification for his solution – that a statement of acknowledgement would be used, not as evidence of an acknowledgement (ie an admission), but as the acknowledgement itself.[58] Lord Hoffmann’s justification was subsequently disapproved by the UK House of Lords[59] because his Lordship’s distinction between admissions and acknowledgements was difficult to draw.[60] Perhaps, this is because Lord Hoffmann’s distinction undermines the collaboration between procedure and substantive law; Lord Hope (taking another bite at the without-prejudice cherry) opined that “this is not a situation in which arguments that resort to procedural … technicalities are appropriate”.[61]

 

D.    Procedure Effectuates Substantive Law

 

Finally, procedure effectuates substantive law. As Lord Penzance in Kendall v Hamilton[62] said, procedure is “the machinery of the law”.[63]

This perhaps obvious point is vividly illustrated in Family Food Court v Seah Boon Lock,[64] where the Court of Appeal considered an agent’s claim for substantial damages in contract for loss suffered by its (identifiable) undisclosed principal. The substantive law was controversial, with “conflicting arguments” whether to award the agent substantial damages for its loss.[65] Fortunately, procedure had a “simple … solution” for achieving substantive justice: awarding the principal substantial damages for its loss by joining it as a party, whether on parties’ application, of the court’s own motion or by the court’s inherent power.[66] If the principal decides not to join, it cannot re-open the case,[67] presumably for abuse of process.

It seems ironic that, in trying to achieve substantive justice, substantive law tied itself up in knots. Instead, procedure cut the Gordian knot and “obviate[d] all the difficulties [vis-à-vis recovery of damages]”, awarding the principal its “full measure of damages”[68] and achieving the full extent of substantive justice. But it is unsurprising, for procedure has secreted substantive law since the 12th century. Substantive law’s recent growth spurt (at least since the Judicature Acts[69]) may obscure this. But when substantive law inadvertently throws in a spanner, procedure still restarts the law’s machinery.

 

III.              Conclusion

 

Part II discusses how more recent cases have adopted a conceptually different approach, where procedure and substantive law are not conflicting concepts in a tension to be resolved, but harmonious aspects of the orb of justice to be integrated.

 



*LLB (First Class Honours) (NUS), LLM (Melb) (w.e.f. 26 July 2020). A version of this article was submitted as a mid-term assignment for the NUS Law module LL4413 Civil Justice and Procedure. I would like to thank Professor Jeffrey Pinsler, SC (Geoffrey Bartholomew Professor, NUS Law) for his kind and helpful comments. All errors and views expressed in this article remain my own.

 

[1] H Patrick Glenn, Legal Traditions of the World: Sustainable Diversity in Law, 5th ed (Oxford: OUP, 2014) at 242.

[2] Supreme Court of Judicature Act, 1873 (UK), 36 & 37 Vict, c 66; Supreme Court of Judicature Act, 1875 (UK), 38 & 39 Vict, c 77.

[3] See Jeffrey Pinsler & Cavinder Bull, “Procedure’s multi-faceted relationship with substantive law: Not a ‘mistress’; nor a ‘handmaid’” in Yeo Tiong Min, Hans Tjio & Tang Hang Wu, gen eds, SAL Conference 2011: Developments in Singapore Law between 2006 and 2010 – Trends and Perspectives (Singapore: SAL Publishing, 2011) [Pinsler & Bull (2011)] at [2].

[4] Re Arbitration between Coles and Ravenshear [1907] 1 KB 1 at 4.

[5] Lee Chee Wei v Tan Hor Peow Victor [2007] 3 SLR(R) 537, [2007] SGCA 22 at [82].

[6] United Overseas Bank Ltd v Ng Huat Foundations Pte Ltd [2005] 2 SLR(R) 425, [2005] SGHC 50 [UOB] at [8]–[9] [emphasis in original].

[7] Pinsler & Bull (2011), supra note 3. See also Jeffrey Pinsler, “The Ideals in the Proposed Rules of Court” (2019) 31 SAcLJ 987 at section II.

[8] Ibid at [2].

[9] UOB, supra note 6, at [9] [emphasis removed].

[10] Ibid.

[11] Supra note 2.

[12] [2000] 3 SLR(R) 745, [2000] SGHC 241.

[13] Ibid at [3], [21].

[14] Ibid at [17], [21].

[15] Ibid at [21].

[16] Ibid at [16].

[17] Ibid at [17].

[18] Ibid at [18].

[19] Ibid at [22].

[20] [2009] 4 SLR(R) 254, [2009] SGHC 143.

[21] Ibid at [129].

[22] Ibid at [127].

[23] Ibid at [126].

[24] Ibid at [130]; as noted by the SGHC, such circumstances are “infinitely varied”.

[25] Ibid.

[26] Breezeway Overseas Ltd v UBS AG [2012] 4 SLR 1035, [2012] SGHC 170 at [20], citing Nichia Corp v Argos Ltd [2007] EWCA Civ 741 at [51].

[27] Ngiam Kong Seng v Lim Chiew Hock [2008] 3 SLR(R) 674, [2008] SGCA 23 at [40], citing Richardson v Mellish (1824) 2 Bing 229 at 252, 130 ER 294 at 252, 303.

[28] See Ngiam Kong Seng v Lim Chiew Hock [2008] 3 SLR(R) 674, [2008] SGCA 23 at [40], citing Enderby Town Football Club Ltd v Football Association Ltd [1971] Ch 591 at 606.

[29] [2007] 3 SLR(R) 40, [2007] SGCA 25 [Greenline].

[30] [2006] 1 WLR 2066 [Bradford].

[31] Greenline, supra note 29 at [17]–[19].

[32] Ibid at [22].

[33] [2014] 2 SLR 318, [2014] SGCA 5 at [93].

[34] See ibid at [93].

[35] [2009] 4 SLR(R) 769, [2009] SGHC 177 [Cytec].

[36] Ibid at [36].

[37] See Evidence Act (Cap 97, 1997 Rev Ed Sing), s 23(1); Limitation Act (Cap 163, 1996 Rev Ed Sing), s 26(2).

[38] Cap 163, 1996 Rev Ed Sing.

[39] Cap 97, 1997 Rev Ed Sing.

[40] Cytec, supra note 35.

[41] Ibid at [15], [27]–[28].

[42] [2019] 3 SLR 874, [2018] SGHCF 18.

[43] Cap 4, 2012 Rev Ed Sing.

[44] Cap 122, 1985 Rev Ed Sing, s 3.

[45] UKM, supra note 42 at [148].

[46] Bradford, supra note 30 at [73].

[47] Cytec, supra note 35 at [36].

[48] Bradford, supra note 30 at [25].

[49] Ibid at [34], [74].

[50] Ibid at [74].

[51] Ibid at [3], [38], [74].

[52] Ibid at [16].

[53] Ibid at [16], [18].

[54] Cytec, supra note 35 at [36].

[55] Bradford, supra note 30 at [18].

[56] Ibid at [16]. See KLD Residential CC v Empire Earth Investments 17 (Pty) Ltd (1135/2016) [2017] ZASCA 98, [2017] 3 All SA 739 at [39], where the Supreme Court of Appeal of South Africa, applying Bradford, held, “Where acknowledgements of liability … would interrupt the running of prescription, such acknowledgements should be admissible, even if made without prejudice during settlement negotiations, but solely for the purpose of interrupting prescription. … The admission remains protected in so far as proving the existence and the quantum of the debt is concerned.”

[57] See Bradford, supra note 30 at [16].

[58] Ibid at [16].

[59] See Ofulue v Bossert [2009] 2 WLR 749.

[60] Ibid at [43], [51], [95].

[61] Ibid at [7].

[62] (1879) 4 App Cas 504.

[63] Ibid at 525.

[64] [2008] 4 SLR(R) 272, [2008] SGCA 31.

[65] Ibid at [60], [62].

[66] Ibid at [63]. In Re Nalpon Zero Geraldo Mario [2013] 3 SLR 258, [2013] SGCA 28, VK Rajah JA (as his Honour then was) observed that “inherent power” was not synonymous with “inherent jurisdiction” (at [33]), given the distinction between jurisdiction (the authority to hear and determine a dispute) and power (the capacity to give effect to the determination of a dispute) (at [31]).

[67] Ibid at [65]–[67].

[68] Ibid at [63].

[69] Supra note 2.